MENTAL
 Main Menu
 Comparisons
 MENTAL vs. Universal Logic


MENTAL vs. Universal Logic
 MENTAL vs.
UNIVERSAL LOGIC

"Universal logic is the general study of logical structures" (Jean-Yves Béziau).

"Logic is not a doctrine, but a reflection of the world. Logic is transcendental" (Wittgenstein, Tractatus 6.13).

"When our minds are fixed on inference, it seems natural to take 'implication' as the fundamental primitive relation" (Bertrand Russell).



Universal Logic

Antecedents

The past 20th century has witnessed the birth of a great variety of logics or logic systems. The list is almost endless [see Problematics - Limitations of Logic]: All these logics were born not only as philosophical theories or to formalize mathematical theories but also to cover needs in other fields where semantics plays a primary role: computer science, artificial intelligence, cognitive science, etc.

Faced with this proliferation of logics, there are two opposing positions. Some think that these systems are mere formal games without meaning, since there is only one logic, the only true logic: classical logic. Others believe that these systems provide value because, depending on the domain, a different logic must be used, that classical logic is not the only one that exists and that it is insufficient.

Traditionally, logic has been considered as the theory or science of the laws of valid or correct human reasoning. Just as there are laws that govern the physical world, our reason also functions according to certain laws. Therefore these laws should be fixed, immutable and universal.

We can ask ourselves several questions on the subject of human reasoning: Currently (and surprisingly) there is no universally accepted notion of what logic or logical system is. We can also ask ourselves questions about logic: Classical (Aristotelian) logic has been considered for centuries the "only" possible logic −and, therefore, universal−, until other logics appeared. It happened the same as with Euclidean geometry, which was considered the "only possible geometry", until non-Euclidean geometries appeared, based on different axiomatic systems.

Aristotle was the first to create a logic as a theory of reasoning: the syllogism. Considered the founder of logic, he also established three major logical principles: the principle of non-contradiction, the principle of the excluded third party and the principle of identity.

Before Aristotle, the Greeks introduced a new form of reasoning: the reductio ad absurdum, whose main representative was Zeno of Elea. It is a reasoning that takes as a hypothesis the opposite of what is considered true. If a contradiction is reached, the assumption is true.

After Aristotelian logic, new logics appeared, such as binary logic, propositional logic and first-order predicate logic. Classical logic was formalized, becoming "mathematical logic".


Universal logic

There have been various attempts to elaborate a universal logic with which all kinds of reasoning could be formalized and all kinds of logics could be specified. Many creators of particular logics considered their logics as universal, since they claimed that they were useful for all kinds of situations, including the logic used in science and in everyday life. These were the cases, for example, of Stanislaw Lesniewski (mereological logic), Jean-Yves Girard (linear logic), Jaakko Hintikka (IF logic) and Ross Brady (relevant logic).

The concept of "universal logic" was introduced in the 1990s by the French-Swiss logician Jean-Yves Béziau, although it has several antecedents, notably in the work of Tarski in the early 20th century.

For Béziau, universal logic is a general theory of the different existing logics or of the different logical structures. Therefore, universal logic is not a logic, neither particular nor universal. From the point of view of the theory of universal logic, the existence of a universal logic is not possible. Logic is not absolute or generic, it is relative or particular in each domain, which has its own laws.

The characteristics of universal logic are: The first "World Congress and School on Universal Logic" took place in Montreaux (Switzerland) in 2005. In 2007 the journal "Logica Universalis" started publication.


The precedent of universal algebra

Universal algebra provides a guide to universal logic. Just as universal algebra is the general study of algebra, universal logic is the general study of logic.

While universal algebra is a recognized field, universal logic has only been recognized in recent times, most likely because of resistance to considering any other kind of logic than classical logic.

In algebra, 3 levels of abstraction are distinguished:
  1. Specific algebra. It uses specific elements. For example, the group of integers under the operation of addition.

  2. Abstract algebra. It abstracts the elements through the use of variables. It does not consider the nature of the objects and only considers the laws obeyed by those objects. For example, the definition of group, with a binary operation that complies with the associative, neutral element and inverse element laws.

  3. Universal algebra. It admits any set of operations with the laws relating different operations. The laws are defined by equations.
According to the theory of universal algebra, there is no single algebra and there are no absolute laws of algebra. Similarly, according to the theory of universal logic, there is no single logic and there are no absolute laws of logic, not even the classical laws of Aristotelian logic: non-contradiction, excluded third and identity.

Following the analogy with algebra, there are 3 levels of abstraction in logic:
  1. Specific logic. It uses specific logical elements. For example, truth values under logical operations.

  2. Abstract logic. It abstracts logical elements by using variables. It does not consider the logical nature of objects and only considers the laws obeyed by those objects.

  3. Universal logic. As in the case of universal algebra, universal logic is not a universal system but a universal systematization. It is a set of general concepts and techniques that make it possible to unify the treatment of different logical systems.

The relation between logic and mathematics

The relationship between logic and mathematics, reflected in mathematical logic, is ambiguous. On the one hand, we have that mathematical logic is the mathematical formalization of logic. On the other hand, mathematical logic can be considered to be the logic of mathematics. This dual aspect of mathematical logic has been reflected in the history of modern logic:
  1. Fregean logic (by Gottlob Frege) was the attempt to reduce mathematics to logic. The Fregean approach corresponds to the logic of mathematics.

  2. Boolean logic (by George Boole) tried to formalize mathematically (algebraically) the laws of thought. The Boolean approach corresponds to the mathematical formalization of logic.
Frege is considered the father of modern logic, for he was the originator of first-order predicate logic. He used a two-dimensional (graphical) notation, which cannot properly be considered a mathematical language.

Boole was the originator of propositional (or binary) logic, formalized as an algebra (the algebra of logic). The algebra of logic was introduced by Boole in his work "Mathematical Analysis of Logic" (1847) and further developed in his book "An Investigation of the Laws of Thought" (1854).

According to the intuitionist school, logic derives from mathematics. According to the logicist school, mathematics derives from logic. Today, logic is considered to be part of mathematics.


The universalism of Boolean logic

Boole's work was extraordinary in its simplicity and affected not only logic. It had a great impact on all orders, taking an important step towards universality: In short, Boole's achievement was extraordinary because its simplicity implied universality.


Paraconsistent logic and universalism

Classical logic is a logic in which the Aristotelian principle of non-contradiction governs. This principle states that a sentence is either true or false, a principle that has been the basis of reasoning for over 2000 years.

But paraconsistent logic questions this principle. Graham Priest [1987] claims that the invention of paraconsistent logic is the most important event ever produced in logic. Although it has precedents in Aristotle himself, the Russian Nicolai Vasiliev and the Pole Jean Lukasiewicz are considered the main precursors of paraconsistent logic.

Vasiliev presented in 1910 (in a lecture at Kazan University) an "imaginary logic" without the principle of non-contradiction. He named it so by analogy with Lobatchevsky's imaginary (non-Euclidean) geometry. He is also considered a precursor of polyvalent and intuitionistic logics. His style was informal but conceptually rich, and he did not go so far as to construct a formal system of paraconsistent logic: For his part, Lukasiewicz also considered the possibility of creating a logic that violated the principle of non-contradiction, but he did not elaborate any logical system reflecting his intuitions either. In 1920 he introduced trivalent logic, which, in a sense, overflowed the limits of classical Aristotelian logic.

In classical logic, a contradiction causes anything to be deduced: every well-formed logical expression is a theorem. A trivial system is that every well-formed formula is a theorem. This feature is called the "explosion principle", formally reflected in the so-called "Scoto's law": α, ¬α ⇒ β

Paraconsistent logic rejects the explosion principle. It studies nontrivial inconsistent systems.

The great promoters of modern paraconsistent logic are the Brazilian mathematician, logician and philosopher Newton da Costa and the philosopher and logician Graham Priest.

The term "paraconsistent logic" was coined by the Peruvian philosopher and journalist Francisco Miró Quesada at the III Latin American Conference of Mathematical Logic in 1976. This term was quickly accepted and disseminated.

Paraconsistent logic is a generic or universal logic that is less restrictive than classical logic and encompasses a wide range of logics. It includes Heyting's intuitionistic logic, fuzzy logic, and other non-classical logics.

Paraconsistent logic is not restricted only to the realm of pure logic but has spread to many fields of application: artificial intelligence (automatic reasoning), robotics, cybernetics, control systems, quantum physics, etc.

Vasiliev considered himself a "logical heretic" for doubting an age-old conviction of mankind. Today this "heresy" is an essential part of modern logic. The principle of non-contradiction plays in logic what the postulate of parallels plays in Euclid's geometry.


MENTAL vs. Universal Logic

The term "universal logic" to refer to the general theory of the different existing logics is poorly chosen because it is an oxymoron. It implicitly implies that there is a universal logic: because it says that it is a logic and that it also has the qualifier of universal. To speak of universal logic makes as little sense as to speak of universal arithmetic or universal geometry. What does make sense is to speak of abstract logic, in which variables are used. Abstract arithmetic is algebra. Some logical results obtained with MENTAL are the following:

Addenda

Myths and paraconsistency

Myths are essentially paraconsistent or inconsistent. The "mytho-logic" is a kind of pseudo-logic where contradictory and paradoxical beings appear: incarnate gods, virgin mothers, etc. In myths there is no subordination to any rule, there is no space or time, every conceivable relationship is possible because everything is interrelated, everything is on the same plane, anything can happen and creativity is total. All myths are potentially the same myth, for they evoke a transcendental world, the world of all possibilities, the world of pure consciousness, where there are no restrictive laws.
Bibliography