MENTAL
 Main Menu
 Comparisons
 MENTAL vs. Montague Grammar


MENTAL vs. Montague Grammar
 MENTAL vs. MONTAGUE GRAMMAR

A formal philosophy project

"There is, in my opinion, no important theoretical difference between natural languages and the artificial languages of logicians; indeed I consider it possible to integrate the syntax and semantics of both kinds of languages within a simple, natural, mathematically precise theory."(Richard Montague)



Montague's Grammar

Richard Montague, American logician, mathematician, and philosopher of language, was a disciple of Alfred Tarsky −one of the great logicians, sometimes compared to Aristotle, Frege, and Gödel− and professor of logic at UCLA.

Montague's grammar is a universal theory of language, in its two aspects of natural (or ordinary) language and formal (or logical) language. Montague was convinced that natural languages and formal languages shared the same principles and could therefore be formalized by a mathematical theory integrating the syntax and semantics of both types of languages.

Montague believed that these common principles of natural and artificial languages could be described by a universal grammar. In the late 1960s, Montague undertook the project of creating such a grammar: a syntactic-semantic-pragmatic system for describing expressions of natural and artificial languages. The result was later called "Montague grammar" or "Montague semantics", since Montague's main goal was the formalization of semantics.

Montague's grammar was a milestone that changed the view of the relationship between formal logic and natural language. Before Montague, logicians considered natural language too ambiguous and unstructured for formal logical analysis. And linguists believed that formal languages were too limited and rigid to capture the structures of natural languages. But a large segment of linguists sought an integration of the cognitive and formal perspectives of natural language. It was in this sense that Montague's work had an impact, since his system allowed syntactic (formal) and semantic (conceptual) structures to be closely connected. The idea that a natural language (such as English) could be formalized by means of logical techniques was very groundbreaking at the time.

Montague, in creating his grammar, had a philosophical motivation: the philosophical task is precisely the investigation of the logical-semantic structure of natural language. Montague's project can be considered as an attempt to create a formal philosophy.

For the development of his project, Montague integrated 5 tools to create the first "mathematically precise" semantic theory of natural language:
  1. Set theory.

  2. Categorial grammar.
    A categorial grammar is a formalism for defining the syntax of natural language. It consists of a set of basic syntactic categories (associated with signs) and a formalism for combining those basic categories to define derived (also called "functional") categories. Normally, the formalism used are syntactic rules.

  3. Church's lambda calculus.
    The lambda calculus (or lambda abstraction) was created by Alonzo Church (1932-1933) as a general theoretical framework for functional expressions. A functional expression is a function defined from other functions. Kleene and Rosser (1936) showed that the lambda calculus was inconsistent. Church then developed (1940) a functional theory of explicit types − a simple, elegant and precise theory−, based on or inspired by Russell's type theory. Church's original lambda calculus had no types. Church's lambda calculus is the foundation of functional programming.

    In Church's type theory, functional expressions are classified into types, and types restrict the combinatorial forms of those expressions. Types are categories of functions and play a role analogous to that of set types in set theory.

  4. Intensional logic.
    Intensional logic deals with the dual nature of all expression: the deep level of meaning (sense or intension) and the surface level of denotation (reference or extension), as well as the relations between the two. The intension (or sense) of an expression is a function of the expression and its "possible state of affairs" or context. In first-order predicate logic, intension plays no role; everything is superficial.

    Although Frege provided a first approximation to the subject (through the concepts of "sense" and "reference"), it was Church who formalized it intensional logic in 1951.

    Montague merged intensional logic and Church's type theory to create his own version of intensional logic, in which the possible state of affairs was represented by the context of the expression, defined as an "index" [see Addenda].

    The version of intensional logic created by Montague has three salient features:

    1. It allows higher-order logical expressions. In a first-order predicate logic, only variables for individual entities are allowed. In higher-order logic, properties can be variables.

    2. Consider functions as generic expressions, where parameters play a role equivalent to quantifiers. It is precisely the operator that makes it possible to differentiate between the particular and the generic. If &lamda; appears in a formula, it is a generic expression (the intent). If it does not appear, we are dealing with a particular formula (the extension).

    3. A theory of higher-order intensional types, based on Church's theory of types.

  5. Tarski's model theory.
    This theory was presented in his famous (and lengthy) 1933 paper "The Concept of Truth in Formalized Languages". In it he describes the meanings of formal and natural languages by defining classes of objects associated with linguistic expressions. Montague extended this theory so that it could be applied to formal semantics.
The essential ideas of Montague's grammar appeared in three seminal papers:
  1. "Universal Grammar" (1970). Here he presents his theory of syntax and formal semantics applied to natural and artificial languages. It was the first attempt to formalize the semantics of natural language.

  2. "English as a Formal Language" (1970). Here he makes more explicit the similarities between the two types of languages and where he argues that there is no important theoretical difference between the two.

  3. "The Proper Treatment of Quantification in Ordinary English" (1973). This article is considered the most important, the one that had the greatest impact, and is often referred to in abbreviated form as "PTQ". In this text he demonstrates the application of his theory to a "fragment" (subset) of English. English sentences are translated into logical expressions (of intensional logic) which in turn are interpreted with Tarski's model theory, i.e. by assigning classes to the expressions of intensional logic. The formalization of the syntax and semantics of English did this by means of an intermediate intensional logic-formal language called L0, a combination of intensional logic of semantic types and lambda abstraction.

Foundations of Montague grammar

Montague grammar is rather cryptic and confusing. However, we can distinguish the following aspects:
MENTAL vs. Montague's Grammar

We can distinguish the following aspects: In conclusion, the expression "formalizing semantics" is contradictory because semantics belongs to the internal (or deep) world and formalizing it would be to bring it to the surface, to the external world. Semantics cannot be formalized without relying on syntax and connecting the two in a biunivocal way. MENTAL is a universal language and a universal grammar. It is simpler than Montague's complex grammar. It represents the syntax-semantics connection in a simple, natural and effective way. It allows formalizing all kinds of expressions, since it is based on the primary archetypes common to mind and nature. MENTAL simplifies and clarifies things by using only the primary archetypes, which are the deepest syntax-semantic resources available.



Addenda

On Montague's grammar

Montague's interest in semantics arose when he taught logic at UCLA and set his students exercises in translating natural language sentences into formal logic. Montague managed to devise a mechanical method for performing these conversions. This method was based on the application of a theoretical model relating syntax and semantics and interpreting natural language sentences in terms of intensions.

The term "Montague grammar" was coined by Barbara Partee, his colleague at UCLA and the person most instrumental in spreading Montague's ideas in linguistics. The term "Montague grammar" first appeared published in [Rodman, 1972].

The importance of the lambda abstraction in Montague's grammar should be emphasized for its expressive capacity for generic, intensional, functional, and higher-order predicates. This importance was reflected by Barbara Partee with the statement "Lambdas truly changed my life" [Partee, 1996].

Montague's grammar constituted a milestone in the development of the formal semantics of natural languages. After Chomsky's revolution, which applied formal (mathematical) methods to syntax, Montague's grammar was a revolution in semantics, which also applied formal methods.

The impact of the publication of PTQ (1973) was very important for semantics, as Chomsky's "Syntactic Structures" (1957) was in its day for syntax. Montague's grammar was developed at about the same time as Chomsky's generative grammar, which used an exclusively syntactic approach. It also appeared at a time when several ways of formalizing semantics were being attempted. The two most important were: interpretive semantics (Jackendoff), which distinguished between syntactic and semantic rules; and generative semantics (Lakoff, Ross, McCawley, Postal), which did not distinguish between these two types of rules. Montague's system harmonized these two approaches, since it contemplated different rules for syntax and semantics, but connected to each other.

Montague's original grammar has been the subject of detailed study by linguists, logicians, and philosophers. Several aspects of his work have already been superseded, but, after his untimely death, his work has subsequently been continued and extended by other linguists. Montague's ideas changed the landscape of formal semantics forever, and he has served as an inspiration for new areas of research in the common ground between logic and linguistics.

Montague's three seminal publications were at the time considered rather cryptic, difficult to understand. Barbara Partee presented Montague's grammar in a more comprehensible way. Her work "Montague Grammar" [1976] is considered the introductory text to Montague's grammar. Another introductory text is that of [Dowty et al., 1981].

In [Thomason, 1979] all of Montague's essays on natural language semantics are collected. The most relevant essays are included in [Thomason, 1977].


Index

The meaning of some natural language expressions by themselves is incomplete, and can only be completed within a context. For example, expressions such as "this", "that", "that", "that", "here", "there", "I", "me", "your", "the", "people", etc. acquire full meaning if the context in which they appear is taken into account. They are context-dependent expressions.

The (triadic) equation "expression+context = meaning" must be considered in these cases. An index, indexical or indicating expression is one whose reference cannot be determined without knowing the context of use. An index "points to" or "indicates" a context, a state of affairs, and is part of the pragmatics of communication in general. There may be higher order indexes (meta-contexts, contexts of contexts).

The word "pragmatics" refers to the possible contexts of use of a language. In order to interpret a pragmatic language, one must determine the set of all possible contexts of use or all aggregates of relevant aspects of possible contexts of use.

The term "index" comes from Peirce, who considered that the index transcended language. For this author, a sign has two kinds of meaning: referential (context-independent) and indexical (context-dependent).


Bibliography