MENTAL vs. Lingua Characteristica Universalis, by Leibniz
MENTAL vs. Leibniz's Lingua Characteristica Universalis
MENTAL vs. LEIBNIZ'S LINGUA CHARACTERISTICA UNIVERSALIS
"To generate the whole from nothing, the one is enough" (Leibniz).
"I do not conceive of any reality without genuine unity" (Leibniz).
"A metaphysical reality sustains and engenders the material universe" (Leibniz).
The Philosophy of Leibniz
The principles
Gottfied Leibniz −philosopher, mathematician, scientist, historian, jurist, librarian and politician− was a universal genius. He made important contributions in very diverse fields: metaphysics, epistemology, mathematics, logic, physics, chemistry, economics, geology, philosophy of language, philosophy of mind, philosophy of religion, jurisprudence and history. King George I of Great Britain described him as "a walking encyclopedia".
Leibniz's philosophy is based on a number of interrelated principles:
Principle of harmony. The universe is a harmonious system in which there is both unity and multiplicity, and where the parts are both differentiated and coordinated with each other. The harmony of the world manifests itself most fully in the harmony of knowledge.
Principle of continuity. Nature is continuous, it does not make leaps (natura non facit saltus). Every possible spatial or temporal position is occupied. There is no empty space and no empty time. Because of continuity, everything is related to everything, from the infinitely small to the infinitely large. The entire body of knowledge is also continuous. The infinitesimal calculus was one of Leibniz's ways of formalizing this principle.
Principle of completeness, The principle of continuity and the principle of completeness imply each other: nature is complete because it is continuous, and vice versa. The universe is complete, in which every place is occupied by a single thing that is distinct from the others. No two things in nature are alike.
Principle of universality. Everything particular derives (or is a manifestation) of the universal. Everything is based on the universal. Knowledge must be one and capable of apprehending the essential connections between all things. Since all things are interconnected, reality must emanate from a single source. All the diversity we observe in the universe is the product of a simple, beautiful and elegant set of ideas. This is the reason for its comprehensibility.
In this sense, Leibniz's project had a fundamental pillar: the construction of a universal language that he called "Lingua Characteristica Universalis" (LCU), a language based on a few simple concepts and capable of expressing all possible ideas by combination of those primary concepts. This universal language would allow the construction of a universal science and a complete encyclopedia of human knowledge.
Principle of non-contradiction (or identity). A proposition cannot be true and false at the same time, a thing A is A and cannot be non-A. It applies to necessary things. This principle is the foundation of logic and mathematics.
Principle of sufficient reason. Nothing happens just because, but because there is a reason. The reason can be a necessity, a justification or a cause. It applies to contingent things. It is a complementary principle to the principle of non-contradiction and allows to connect mathematics with natural philosophy. For example, "Caesar passed the Rubicon". If such a thing happened it was because something must have motivated him.
This principle is the foundation of experimental science. It is the foundation of all truth in the natural world because it makes it possible to establish the condition (the reason) for the truth of a proposition. Without a sufficient reason one cannot affirm when a proposition is true.
Principle of perfection. This world is the most perfect of all possible worlds. This principle is an application of the principle of sufficient reason. There are infinitely many possible worlds, but only one has come into existence, which is the best of all possible worlds, the most perfect, the fullest, and the simplest. God maximizes the variety of the world while minimizing the laws that generate that diversity.
In possible worlds the principle of non-contradiction operates. Every possible world is non-contradictory. Every possible world becomes actual to the extent that there is a sufficient reason. Each part of the world makes possible the maximum perfection of the totality. In the best of possible worlds nature does not make leaps and nothing happens all at once.
Principle of identity of indiscernibles (also called "Leibniz's law"). Two things are identical if and only if they share the same properties.
Truths of reason and truths of fact
According to Leibniz, truths of reason are necessary propositions, that is, they cannot be denied. Their negation implies contradiction. Truths of reason are based on the principle of non-contradiction, they are self-evident or reducible to others that are necessarily true. Mathematical truths are an example of truths of reason. They are a priori truths.
Within the truths of reason are the "identical" truths, which are known by intuition and are self-evident.
The truths of fact are contingent. They refer to the sphere of possibility. Everything that exists in reality could be otherwise. Its negation is possible. The opposite of a factual truth is conceivable. For example, "Columbus discovered America" is a factual truth because it could have been the opposite way (Columbus did not discover America). They are based on the principle of sufficient reason. They are a posteriori truths.
Monads
Monadology was Leibniz's contribution to metaphysics. It is described in his work "Monadology" (1714), a short text written toward the end of his life. Leibniz saw the universe as consisting of fundamental entities which he called "monads". This term comes from the Greek "monas", meaning "unity" or "logos". Monadology would come to be the treatise on monads or the science of unity.
Leibniz was against the Cartesian dualism mind-body and thought-extension. He harmonized the monistic (the inextensive and substantial) and the pluralistic (the manifestations of substances in the world). In this way, Leibniz harmonized theology and philosophy.
According to Leibniz, the universe is full, it is full of "monads", the characteristics of which are as follows:
They are simple, perfect, indivisible, single substances, without parts and without extension.
Having no extension, they have no form (or shape).
They are the ultimate constituents of reality. They are principles or categories that are the foundation of all that exists, the source of all that is manifested. They are the foundation of the unity of all things.
They are different from the atoms of the Greeks Leucippus and Democritus, since atoms are physical and have form. Monads are "metaphysical atoms", they are spiritual substances, not spatio-temporal entities.
They are independent. They do not interact with each other, but are linked by pre-established harmony. They do not have windows open to the outside that allow interactions in the manner of physical interactions.
Although simple, monads have internal attributes or states. Monads differ from each other by their internal attributes. They are different expressions of the same total reality.
The attributes or internal states of monads can change. The changes have their origin in the monads themselves, not outside.
They reflect each other and reflect the universe. They are mirrors reflecting other mirrors. They are, in themselves, universes.
They are self-sufficient. They are governed by their own laws. A monad "knows" what to do at any given moment. These laws can be regarded as analogous to the physical laws governing subatomic particles.
They have perceptions or apperceptions. Perceptions encompass and represent a multiplicity in a unity. Apperception is awareness (or reflective knowledge of their internal state).
There is a hierarchy of monads. The supreme monad is God, pure consciousness, the beginning and end of all things, the source and reason of all established order. There are inorganic monads (unconscious perception), vegetable monads (weak perception), sensitive monads (sensitive perceptions), rational monads (conscious perception) and pure monads (those of the angels),
The reality we perceive are manifestations of monads. The monads, although simple, are part of the compounds (the manifestations). Everything is constituted of monads.
They have the capacity for action. They are centers of force or energy. They give the bodies in which they manifest their inertia and impenetrability.
The bodies are subordinate to the monads. There is a pre-established harmony by God between monad and body. The harmony between body and soul is illustrated by the metaphor of the watchmaker (God) who sets the clocks synchronized.
The world of monads is regulated by ends; the corporeal world, by causality. There are two worlds: the intelligible world of substances and the visible world of bodies.
The Lingua Characteristica Universalis, of Leibniz
Leibniz devoted his whole life to the great project of creating a universal language that would be useful for reasoning, for the discovery of truth and as a tool to enhance human thought (in the same way that a microscope or telescope enlarges our vision). I knew Llull's Ars Magna. He also knew Descartes' work on the Mathesis Universalis (it is known from a letter he wrote to Mersenne in 1629).
Leibniz did not intend to create a language for human communication (spoken and written), although he devoted time and effort to study this subject, for he was fascinated by the richness and plurality of natural languages. He considered the idea of simplifying the grammar of Latin, something similar to what Peano tried at the end of the 19th century with the latino sine flexione (Latin without declensions). He finally abandoned the universal language project because he saw that it was impossible to discover the mother tongue or Adamic language from which all natural languages must have arisen. From then on he focused on a more viable project: to try to develop a universal language for science, a useful instrument for the discovery of truth.
Leibniz's concern to formulate a universal method for reasoning was set forth in his doctoral thesis De Arte Combinatoria, in 1666 (when he was only 20 years old), where he sets forth his project of constructing an "alphabet of thought" and where he analyzes the power and limits of the art of combination. An alphabet based on simple concepts and in which all other concepts would be combinations of the simple concepts. This project was clearly influenced by Llull's Ars Magna, a work that he considered insufficiently generic and that his Art tried to generalize.
In Elementa Characteristicae Universalis Leibniz developed the principles presented in his doctoral thesis, suggesting to use prime numbers to encode concepts. He attempted to apply a model of arithmetical analysis to concepts in general. The arithmetic model is that every integer is uniquely decomposed into prime factors. Leibniz assigns a "characteristic number" to each attribute. To each entity he assigns the product of the characteristic numbers of its attributes. To find out if an entity has a certain attribute, the characteristic number of the entity is divided by the characteristic number of the attribute. If it is divisible, then the entity has that attribute. For example, the concept "space" is represented by the number 2, the concept "between" by the number 3, and the concept "all" by the number 10. A composite concept, such as "interval" would be expressed as the product of these three numbers: 2*3*10, i.e., "space between all".
Diagram of "Of Combinatorial Art"
In Lingua Generalis he suggested replacing the Arabic numerals 1 to 9 by the letters of the Latin alphabet (b c d f g g k l m n), respectively, and using the vowels (a e i o u) for the units and powers of 10 (1, 10, 100, 1,000, 10,000), respectively. For example, the number 81,374 would be coded as "mubodilefa". This system had the advantage that it allowed the syllables of a word to be permuted.
Characteristics of the Lingua Characteristica Universalis
The characteristics of this universal language were as follows:
Philosophical language.
A philosophical language is one that can be constructed from some first principles or philosophical categories. For Leibniz, true philosophy must be based on a set of simple concepts, distinct from one another and indefinable. "Simple" means that they cannot be defined by means of other concepts. From these simple concepts would be derived, by combinatorics, all other concepts.
Just as all natural numbers are products of prime numbers, so all complex ideas should be combinations of simple ideas. "True philosophy" would have to identify the simple concepts from which all other concepts could be generated, applying simple rules, which would constitute a conceptual (or philosophical) grammar.
In Termini Simpliciores (1680-1684), Leibniz drew up a list of 24 elementary terms reminiscent of Aristotelian categories:
Ens (being), substantia (substance), attributum (attribute), ens positivum (positive being), absolutum (absolute), idem (equal), < i>unum (one), quod sequitur (result), prius (first), posterius (posterior), tale (un), tantum (alone), quod inest (what is), numerus (number), positionem habens (position), mutatio (change), agens (agent), patiens (patient), acturiens (act), extensum (extension), situs (site), quiescere (stop), tendere seu conari (tend or try), vis seu potentia (force or power).
Mathematical language.
Simple concepts would be represented by mathematical type symbols. Simple concepts and their combinations would allow all mathematical concepts to be expressed. The term "characteristica" refers precisely to the fact that the language would be based on characters or signs. The sign is what produces the distinction, and what allows reasoning. For Leibniz, relation gives rise to substance, and not the other way around, as Newton maintained.
Psychological language.
These simple concepts would constitute the "alphabet of thought", whose combinations would make it possible to represent all human knowledge. In this way, mankind would have a new organ aimed at increasing the power of the mind and overcoming our cognitive limitations.
Leibniz said that the universal language was difficult to establish (the simple concepts, their symbolism and their combinatorial rules), but once achieved, it would be easy to learn and intuitive, being founded on the basic operations of human thought.
Scientific language.
Language was to be capable of reflecting reality by means of an analogy or correspondence between the order of the world and the grammatical or formal order of the symbols of language. All sciences would be expressible by means of the LCU. And this language would not only be valid for the formal and natural sciences, but also for the human and social sciences, such as administration, organization, law, etc. All sciences would become branches of the Mathesis Universalis (universal mathematics) −an expression borrowed from Descartes−, which would thus become philosophia perennis.
Symbolic language.
Symbols can be arbitrarily chosen, but not meanings: the relations or correspondences between symbols and things, what is represented by symbols. This correspondence is the foundation of truth. There is a single semantics and many possible formalizations (syntax). Therefore, language should be formalized and interpreted (with associated semantics). There should also be a correspondence or analogy between the structure of the world and the grammatical structure of universal language.
A theory of knowledge and truth.
The LCU would be a theory of knowledge, a theory that tries to lead man to clear knowledge. And it would be a theory of truth, a universal methodology for the search for truth.
Leibniz was the first to turn the problem of the foundations of knowledge into an end. For Leibniz, all truths can be deduced from a small set of simple truths represented by the first concepts.
The encyclopedia of human knowledge would serve for existing knowledge (obtained a posteriori) and to substantiate future discoveries. Combinatorics, on the other hand, refers to the possible knowledge to be obtained a priori.
For Leibniz, all knowledge must have a practical aspect (theoria cum praxi); knowledge must be useful for life (ad usum vitae), to solve practical problems. "The wisdom and power of mankind increases in two ways: on the one hand, with the discovery of new knowledge and new techniques, and on the other hand, with the habitual practice of those already known" [Leibniz, 2009].
Logical language.
The universal language should also be able to act as Calculus Rationator, that is, to be a universal logical calculus framework of a mechanical type, in which it would not be necessary to know the meaning of the symbols. But not as an aid to reasoning, but as a substitution for it, in order to avoid errors and to be sure of truths.
Leibniz was convinced that all problems could be formalized mathematically with his language. And that to solve any problem it would only be necessary to calculate. Thinking would be the same as calculating. The truth would be discovered easily and infallibly, so that polemics and useless controversies would cease.
Leibniz confesses his great admiration for the Aristotelian syllogistic theory, the essence of which is demonstrative. However, he believed that this type of logic was insufficient to deal with complex problems. He wanted to extend and generalize Aristotelian logic and go beyond the closed, complete and perfect system conceived by Kant, to make it a universal method for the discovery of new truths. In this sense, he divided logic into two parts:
The logic of demonstration. It is the traditional logic, which allows to formalize reasoning and deduction. These logical or symbolic calculations would reflect the processes of human thought. "All our reasoning is nothing but connections and substitutions of characters."
The logic of invention. It would be based on the combinatorics of symbols, according to operational logical rules (applied to the basic symbols) to lead from the known to the unknown, to new truths. The real strength of the calculus would reside in the combinatorial rules. This new logic would be an "algebra of thought" or a "general algebra", the art of combining concepts.
Leibniz was one of the first modern philosophers to realize the power of formalism in general, based on representational linguistics, and of reasoning in particular. He wanted to formalize all areas of knowledge, including the demonstrative aspects. His formalization would be based on syntax, semantics and pragmatics. He wanted to systematize all knowledge by means of a universal scientific method (or a science of logic) that would allow him to discover the intelligible structure of the universe and its deep and essential unity. This science of logic he calls "Scientia Generalis" (SG). Once developed, it would be the solution to all the problems of science. It was the task of the SG to discover which of these basic concepts of human thought.
The Calculus Rationator, as a purely formal "blind calculus", anticipates the algebra of logic (Boolean algebra) and the computer language of computers and even artificial intelligence. Leibniz is considered the first scientist of computation. He was the first to think of logic as calculus and as the foundation of mathematics itself. Leibniz is also the inventor of binary arithmetic, an arithmetic with metaphysical implications, since it is a calculation with 0 (associated with nothing) and 1 (associated with everything or God). "To generate the all from nothing, the one is enough". On this subject, Leibniz understood the enormous power of simplicity.
Leibniz built (between 1674 and 1694) a calculating machine, a prototype machine for stepwise mathematical calculations that improved on Pascal's (which only added and subtracted). It was the first machine capable of performing the 4 arithmetic operations (addition, subtraction, multiplication and division). Only two were built. The one in the picture is in the National Library of Lower Saxony.
However, Leibniz wanted to go beyond arithmetic. He dreamed of a logical calculating device. In this sense, the Calculus Rationator could be automated to generalize his arithmetic machine.
The universal philosophical-mathematical-psychological-scientific-symbolic-logical language intuited by Leibniz was not carried to completion because of its overly ambitious character. Leibniz's merit was not only to formulate this great project, but also to try to carry it out throughout his life, an attempt sustained by his universalist philosophy and by the faith he had in the realization of this project.
Nor did he present his new logic, a generalization of Aristotelian logic. And neither, consequently, the universal science nor the complete encyclopedia of human knowledge. The same thing happened to Descartes with his Mathesis Universalis.
However, Leibniz's universalist ideas exerted a remarkable influence on later authors. The historical effects of the LCU are visible today:
Logic: mathematical logic, algebra of logic (Boolean algebra), modal logic (based on the concepts of possibility and necessity).
Mathematics: differential and integral calculus, the formalist and intuitionist paradigms.
Computer science/software: programming languages.
Computer science / hardware: the computer as a universal computing device, where the "instruction set" is the set of primary or simple concepts, and where the programs are the possible ideas that can be expressed.
Computing / web: hypertext. Leibniz wanted the encyclopedia of human knowledge to be structured not by subject, but by "paths" (what today we call navigation through hyperlinks).
Artificial intelligence (AI): AI languages. Leibniz anticipated certain semantics as used today in AI, such as operational rules.
Analytic philosophy. The correspondence between the structure of reality and the structure of language is a conception identical to that of the first Wittgenstein for whom a proposition must have a structure similar to that of the facts it reflects [Tractatus, 2.2 and 4.121].
Psychology: Mentalés, Fodor's hypothetical "language of thought".
Semiotics. Semiotics is the study of signs, their structure and the relationship between signifier and signified.
Fractals. Leibniz conceived the idea of self-similarity. He imagined a circle and inscribed in it 3 equal circles, in these 3 circles another 3 circles can be inscribed, and so on. This procedure can continue indefinitely and provides a good example of the concept of self-similarity.
The fractal imagined by Leibniz
Holograms. "Every portion of matter may be regarded as a garden full of plants or as a pond full of fish. But every branch of the plant, every part of the animal, and every drop of its vital fluids is another similar garden" (Leibniz, Monadology). In 1947, Dennis Gabor described the principle of the hologram using Leibniz's differential and integral calculus
MENTAL and the Lingua Characteristica Universalis
As in the case of the Mathesis Universalis Cartesian, there are numerous parallels between the LCU and MENTAL:
Philosophical language.
Leibniz's LCU is based on philosophical concepts.
MENTAL primitives are philosophical categories.
Mathematical language.
According to Leibniz, philosophy and mathematics go together: "Without mathematics we cannot penetrate deeply into philosophy. Without philosophy we cannot penetrate deeply into mathematics. Without both we cannot penetrate deeply into anything."
MENTAL is the theoretical and practical foundation of mathematics. Its primitives are philosophical and primitive categories of supreme level of abstraction.
Psychological language.
Leizniz's LCU was to be the language of thought and primitive concepts the alphabet of thought.
In MENTAL, the primitives correspond to the primary archetypes, common to the inner and outer world. The alphabet of thought is the alphabet of the world, the essential structure of reality, the philosophical categories. MENTAL is a model of the mind (the inner world) and the external world. Ontology is equal to epistemology.
Leibniz rejected Cartesian mind-body dualism. He believed that there was no interaction between mind and body but only a non-causal relation of harmony, parallelism or correspondence between the two. In this sense, Leibniz was close to the concept of primary archetypes, which manifest themselves at the physical and psychic levels.
Symbolic language.
Leibniz's simple concepts, represented by mathematical-type symbols, are the primary archetypes of MENTAL, represented by symbols. Moreover, the structure of language should correspond to the structure of reality, as is also the case in MENTAL.
Leibniz said that the difficult thing was to find a method to combine the symbols with which the primitives are expressed. In MENTAL, the combinations are made with the primitives themselves. Structural semantics is the same as lexical semantics.
Logical language.
LCU would contemplate traditional logic and "new logic" (combinatorial logic).
MENTAL contemplates the logic of decision and the logic of deduction. Combinatorial logic would be Leibniz's inventive (or creative) logic, the logic that allows the discovery of new truths. More than logic it is a generic or universal algebra.
Compressed language.
Leibniz's LCU would take a compressed form, like MENTAL. It is a principle of economy and universality, by using symbols (of universal meanings) and not keywords (of particular meanings).
Theory of knowledge and theory of truth.
The LCU was to be a foundation of knowledge and truth.
In MENTAL, truth and knowledge are based on the primary archetypes, which allow to represent all kinds of knowledge.
Universal science.
Leibniz was interested in developing a universal science based on his universal language.
MENTAL is the foundation of the unification of knowledge by means of a universal formalization. The frontiers between the various formal sciences are diluted, since they all have the same principles: the archetypes of consciousness.
Problem solver.
Leibniz was convinced that all problems could be formalized with his language, and that problems would be easily solved by calculus. Leibniz believed that his LCU would be a "general problem solver."
MENTAL can indeed be considered a general problem solver because all problems contemplated from the deep level of the primary archetypes are simplified, clarified, solved or dissolved.
Innocent and easy to learn language.
"My invention is an innocent magic, a non-chemical Kabbalah, which everyone can read and which everyone can easily learn" (Leibniz's letter to the Duke of Hannover, April 1679). MENTAL is also an innocent, naive and easy to learn language.
In addition to these aspects, MENTAL adds more features:
Computer language.
Leibniz is considered the "father" of computer science for his invention of the binary system and the logical calculus.
MENTAL is "everything" in computer science: a computational model, the foundation of every operating system, a programming language, a specification language, a database language, etc.
Artificial intelligence language.
Leibniz is considered the forerunner of artificial intelligence.
MENTAL is an artificial intelligence language more powerful than Lisp and Prolog.
Language of Consciousness.
Leibniz made no reference in the LCU to the subject of consciousness. He only did so in the subject of monads.
MENTAL is a language of consciousness because it integrates the primary archetypes and the pairs of opposites or duals.
Language of possible worlds.
The notion of possibility is not formalized in Leibniz's work. In MENTAL, it is formalized, including its dual concept (necessity). MENTAL is the Magna Carta of possible worlds. A more general language than the one conceived by Leibniz.
Leibniz's LCU was not carried to completion because of its overly ambitious character. Descartes, however, was less ambitious and also more fruitful, as was the union of algebra and geometry to give rise to what we know today as "analytic geometry". With MENTAL, with profoundly simple primitives, they produce maximum creativity and maximum fruit.
In conclusion, MENTAL is a proposal for a simple (and at the same time powerful) and abstract universal language, totally in line with the language conceived and sought by Leibniz.
Addenda
Leibniz's infinitesimal calculus
Leibniz came up with the idea of this calculus in 1676 and published his results in 1684. Newton had conceived the same idea some years before Leibniz, but did not publish his results until 1687. The notation proposed by Leibniz was adopted as the simplest, and is still used today.
Gödel and the Lingua Characteristica Universalis
Various authors have believed that Leibniz's universal language project was an unfounded and overly optimistic fantasy. However, Gödel believed that Leibniz's universal language was feasible and that its eventual development would revolutionize mathematics, both theoretically and practically.
Gödel was a lifelong student of Leibniz's work, especially during his four decades at Princeton, when he studied all the works in the university library. He also ordered a copy of Leibniz's voluminous manuscripts.
Gödel discovered that Leibniz's works had been partially censored. Several books published around Leibniz's time referred to paragraphs, passages, pages and chapters of Leibniz's works that did not exist. And that there were practically no concrete and detailed descriptions of his universal language in Leibniz's publications, despite the fact that Leibniz speaks in his writings of "my invention". Gödel interpreted this to mean that there was a systematic conspiracy that had suppressed essential parts of this subject. Gödel was convinced that Leibniz had successfully completed his universal language project. When Gödel was asked about those who had prevented his invention from coming to light, he replied, "Those who wish to prevent people from becoming more intelligent."
Gödel believed that the same group that had censured Leibniz centuries earlier was after him, to prevent people from understanding the true meaning of his own discovery (the incompleteness theorem): that mathematics is not a self-contained (or self-sufficient) system, that it cannot have superficial or formal foundations, and that one had to investigate along the line or philosophy traced by Leibniz, that is, the search for the primary concepts (of the intuitive and deep type) and their combinatorics.
Gödel considered himself the intellectual heir of Leibniz and worked on the search for the philosophical language. He drew up a list of 18 fundamental intuitive categories or concepts: reason, cause, substance, accident, necessity, value, God, cognition, force, time, form, content, matter, life, truth, idea, reality, and possibility.
When his wife (Adele) became ill, and had to be admitted to a hospital, Gödel, without Adele's protection, refused to eat because he was sure they were trying to poison him, and he died of starvation. Gödel's writings on Leibniz are archived in the Firestone Library at Princeton. They are written in archaic 19th century German, in shorthand form, with unconventional mathematical symbolism and Latin phrases (probably original quotations from Leibniz).
On the other hand, Leibniz's formalism is believed to have influenced Gödel in working out his incompleteness theorem. Indeed, there is a certain analogy between Leibniz's system of coding concepts (simple concepts as prime numbers and composite concepts as product of prime numbers) and Gödel's system of coding sentences (gödelization).
Gödel and monadology
Gödel described his general philosophy as a monadology with a structure similar to that of Leibniz [Wang, 1990]. He drew an analogy between monadology and the reflection principle of set theory. This principle refers to the universe or set U of all sets. This set U is said to "reflect" the universe of all sets. According to this principle, if C is a set, U contains C, all its subsets, the set containing all its subsets, and so on. The analogy between monads and U is that in both cases we have a universe of objects, and that each object is a universe that resembles the whole.
Monadology vs. MENTAL
From the time of Leibniz to the present day, with the exception of Gödel, a great follower of Leibniz, monadology has been considered an arbitrary, even eccentric philosophy. It was also too ambitious, claiming to cover everything from God to the inanimate.
However, an analogy can be drawn between Leibniz's monads and MENTAL, in its two aspects: the deep (the primary archetypes) and their manifestations (the expressions), a vision that generalizes Gódel's vision, which is limited only to sets.
This view of monadalogy has its main antecedents in:
Plato, who once called the Ideas or Forms, the antecedents of the present primary archetypes, "monads".
Nicholas of Cusa, who developed a monadology based on the principle that "everything is in everything", a principle he attributed to Anaxagoras. According to this philosopher, the unity of all things (the universe) exists in plurality (the di-verse), and plurality exists in unity. Each thing exists in act "reducing" (reflecting) the whole universe. The universe reduced in each thing makes of each thing a unity that can be called "monad".
Modern fractal theory, where an object with fractal structure contains the same pattern at all scales. And holograms, where the part contains the whole (the entire image) and the whole is also contained in each part. Both structures (fractals and holograms) were conceived by Leibniz.
The characteristics of MENTAL as monadology are:
As a language, it has fractal structure: the same patterns (the primary archetypes) are present in all manifestations (the expressions).
There is a hierarchy of monads: 1) MENTAL is a unit, it is a monad; 2) the set of all possible expressions (); 3) the archetypes; 4) the expressions.
The philosophy of monads is integrated with the universal language (or is equivalent to it).
It is a simple and intelligible monadology.
The archetypes are monads because they are simple, individual, independent, without extension, of metaphysical type. They are the primary elements of reality (philosophical categories). Each one reflects the others. We perceive their manifestations at an abstract level. They represent consciousness or dimensions of consciousness. They are not spatio-temporal, but manifest as abstract space-time.
Possible expressions are also monads, which are manifestations of archetypes. Expressions have the capacity for action and they have their primary and original existence in Ω, the source of all expressions. The hierarchy of monads corresponds to the hierarchy of expressions. Each expression is potentially any other expression, that is, it can be replaced by any other of the infinite possible ones. Expressions are manifestations of consciousness.
Monads in ancient Greek philosophy
The ancient Greek philosophers referred to the monad as the first thing, the seed, the essence, the builder, the foundation, the immutable truth, etc. Numbers only express different qualities of the monad. Unity was not considered a number, but the father of all numbers. Unity exists in all things, but goes unnoticed.
The circle is the source of all subsequent forms, the matrix in which all geometric patterns develop. The Greek term for the principles represented by the circle was "monad," from the root "meneim" (stable being) and "monas" (unity).
Unity is implicitly present in every number, for n×1 = n and n/1 = n. Unity always preserves the identity of everything it encounters.
The monad is the common denominator of the universe. Every circle we see or create is a profound sentence about the transcendental nature of the universe. The center is dimensionless. The periphery has infinite points. The circle represents unity and relates zero (the center) to infinity (the circumference). Relates nothingness to everything. It relates the limited (the surface) and the unlimited of the periphery. Symbolizes unity, eternity and enlightenment. Each circle represents the monad, the complete universe.
Just as 1 is the father of all numbers, the circle is the father of all forms. The point is the essence of a circle. A point has no extension, so it is impossible to draw. Nothing exists without a center that founds it: the nucleus of an atom, the heart of a body, the capital of a nation, the sun of the solar system, the black hole of a galaxy, and so on. The point is the source of everything. A point by expanding creates a circle.
Cohen, C. Jonathan. On the Project of a Universal Character. Mind (New Series) 63:249, 1954.
Couturart, Louis. La Logique de Leibniz. Felix Alcan Editeur, Paris, 1901.
Couturart, Louis. Opuscules et fragments inedits De Leibniz. Nabu Press, 2010.
Couturart, Louis; Lean, Leopold. Histoire de la langue universelle. Hachette, 1903.
Davis, Martin. La computadora universal. De Leibniz a Turing. Debate, 2002.
Eco, Umberto. La búsqueda de la lengua perfecta. Capítulo 14: De Leibniz a la Enciclopedia. Crítica, 1999.
Hampshire, Stuart. The Age of Reason. The 17th Century Philosophers. Mentor Books, 1956.
Hintikka, Jaakko. Lingua Universalis vs. Calculus Ratiocinator. An Ultimate Presupposition of Twentieth-Century Philosophy. Jaakko Hintikka Selected Papers. Springer, 2006.
Jolley, Nicholas. The Cambridge Companion to Leibniz. Cambridge University Press, 1994.
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. Discurso de metafísica. Alianza, 2002.
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. Escritos filosóficos. Antonio Machado, 2003.
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. Nuevos ensayos sobre el entendimiento humano. Alianza, 1992.
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. Monadología. Ediciones Folio, 2003. Disponible en Internet en versión trilingüe (español, frances y latín), con introducción de Gustavo Bueno.
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. Escritos de filosofía política y jurídica. Biblioteca Nueva, 2009.
Loemker, Leroy (ed. y tr.). Leibniz. Philosophical Papers and Letters. Synthese Historical Library. D. Reidel, 1969.
Ortega y Gasset. La idea de principio en Leibniz y la evolución de la teoría deductiva. Alianza, 1992.
Saame, Otto. Ortega y Gasset. El principio de la razón en Leibniz. Laia, 1988.
Sociedad Española Leibniz. www.leibniz.es.
Sociedad Española Leibniz para Estudios del Barroco y la Ilustración. www.leibnizsociedad.org.
Tent, M.B.W. Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. The Polymath Who Brought Us Calculus. A.K. Peters, 2011.
Wang, Hao. Reflections on Kurt Gödel. The MIT Press, 1990.