MENTAL
 Main Menu
 Union of Opposites
 MENTAL, the Union of Meaning and Denotation


MENTAL, the Union of Meaning and Denotation
 MENTAL, THE UNION
OF MEANING
AND DENOTATION

"It is the search for truth that prompts us to advance from meaning to reference" (Frege).



Meaning vs. denotation

Every descriptive linguistic expression has two aspects or dimensions: its meaning and its denotation (or reference). These two aspects are of great importance in logic, mathematics and philosophy (theory of knowledge). Examples:
  1. "The capital of Spain" denotes or refers to "Madrid".

  2. "The author of Don Quixote" denotes "Cervantes".

  3. "Los Reyes Magos de Oriente" denotes "Melchor, Gaspar and Baltasar".

  4. "The planets of the solar system" denotes "Mercury, Venus, Earth, Mars, Jupiter, Saturn, Uranus and Neptune".

  5. "The number of planets in the solar system" denotes the number 8, but the meaning of this expression is not this number. And it is not because the number differs according to the temporal context (today there are 8, but before there were 9, when Pluto was included).
Characteristics: The double dimension meaning-denotation of a linguistic expression makes it possible to clarify or solve important semantic problems, provided that the deep aspect (the meaning) is considered and not the superficial aspect (the denotation).
  1. The problem of identity.
    The identity or equality between two expressions a and b (a = b) should not be understood as denotational equality (between objects), but as equality of meanings. The expressions a and b denote the same object, but through different meanings. The identity is, therefore, of meaning, conceptual. For example, "The capital of France" and "The city of light".

  2. The problem of substitutability.
    According to the principle of substitutability, one can substitute in any proposition one expression for another whenever both refer to or denote the same object. But this principle is not always applicable to any context. For example, if we substitute in the proposition" "I believed that Barcelona was the capital of Spain" the expression "the capital of Spain" for "Madrid", we obtain "I believed that Barcelona was Madrid". Another example is "Madrid was chosen by Philip II as the capital of Spain in 1561". Substituting "the capital of Spain" for "Madrid", we get "Madrid was chosen by Philip II as Madrid in 1561". Therefore, a substitution of an expression in a proposition must be made by meaning, not by reference, so that its meaning is not altered.

  3. The problem of expressions without references (or with empty references).
    In this case, the meaning of these expressions is considered to imply or provide knowledge or information. For example, the expression "Pegasus is a winged horse" is interpreted as carrying information about an entity called Pegasus, regardless of its existential level.
In this issue of the relation between meaning and denotation, different questions can be raised, such as the following:
Frege: Meaning and Reference

The modern understanding of the intensional and extensional aspects of language begins with Gottlob Frege and his famous 1892 article "On Sense and Reference" (Über Sinn und Bedeutung) [Frege, 2003], which had a great impact at the philosophical level. In fact, modern philosophy of language −analytic philosophy− is considered to begin precisely with this article. In it, Frege distinguishes two distinct aspects of linguistic expressions:
  1. The sense of a linguistic expression is the form or manner by which reference is made to an object, the mode of presentation of the reference.

  2. The reference of a linguistic expression is the object to which the expression refers.
Frege's main ideas regarding this subject are:
Russell: Theory of Descriptions

Bertrand Russell's 1905 article "On Denoting" [Russell, 1981] is one of his major contributions to the philosophy of language and one of the most significant and influential philosophical-linguistic essays of the 20th century. It was published in the journal "Mind" in 1905, reprinted in the same journal on its centenary (2005) and in "Logic and Knowledge" in 1956. This article provoked a great philosophical-linguistic debate that has not ceased until today. In it he expounds his "theory of descriptions".

Russell's theory is based on the following ideas:
The problem of descriptions without denotation

Russell's theory offers a solution to the problem of the truth value of a sentence that has no denotation (or reference) so as not to violate the principle of the excluded third party. The paradigmatic example given by Russell is "The present king of France is bald". This sentence can be considered from two points of view:
  1. Logical.
    The sentence must be either true or false, so as not to violate the principle of the excluded third party. At first it seems that the sentence is false, since France is not a monarchy. But if it is false, its converse ("The current king of France is not bald") should be true, which is also not true. Another way of looking at it is that the sentence is not true because among bald people is not the current king of France. And it is not false because among the non-bald people there is not the current king of France either. We are faced with a logical paradox.

  2. Semantic.
    On the one hand, the sentence makes sense (because it is perfectly understood) and on the other hand it does not (because it refers to an entity does not exist (the current king of France).
The solution proposed by Russell to the problem of definite descriptions without reference consists in analyzing the whole sentence ("He/The F is G") and not the definite description in isolation (F). It consists in dividing the sentence "The current king of France is bald" into three components:
  1. There is a x such that x is the current king of France.
  2. There exists no such thing, except x as is the present king of France.
  3. x is bald.
That is, the definite description contains three pieces of information: 1) an implicit existence information; 2) an implicit uniqueness information; 3) a predicate. Then, for the sentence to be true, three conditions must be fulfilled: 1) that the subject of the description exists; 2) that the subject is unique; 3) that the subject has the predicate. In this case, since the first condition is not met, the sentence is false.

And the negation of the sentence affects all of it (broad scope), and not only the predicate (narrow scope). Its negation is not "The current king of France is not bald" but "It is not the case that there is a current king of France and he is bald". Therefore, the sentence is true. In this way, the principle of the excluded third party is not violated. In this case, the negation is included at the beginning of the sentence and its scope is the whole sentence.

Russell's theory also analyzes indefinite descriptions. For example, the sentence "A man is walking" contains the indefinite description "a man", in a place that could be occupied by a proper name. As in the case of definite descriptions, such expressions should not be treated as if they were proper names, but also analyzed logically: "There exists a x such that x is a man and x is walking."


Other Authors

Mill: connotation and denotation

Before Frege, John Stuart Mill in his work "A System of Logic" (1843) [Mill, 2002] discusses denotation, connotation, and other linguistic issues:
Church: meaning and denotation

Frege provided the basic ideas about in his famous 1892 article, but he did not formalize them into a logical theory. In 1951, Alonzo Church published an article [Church, 1951] in which he described a formal logic (intensional logic) in which every term (including variables) had sense (or meaning) and denotation (or reference).

The logic Church elaborated was very complex and not very general. It was based on Russell's type theory and the lambda calculus (the functional calculus created by Church himself).


Carnap: intension and extension

Carnap −one of the leading exponents of the Vienna Circle− extended and formalized the ideas of Frege and Church. He expounded them mainly in his work "Meaning and Necessity" [Carnap, 2008]. In this work, Carnap expounds a new method for the semantic analysis of meaning, i.e., for analyzing and describing the meaning of linguistic expressions. This method generalizes classical concepts known as class and property. Carnap's system is not a homogeneous formal system and is very complex. Nevertheless, Carnap's ideas had a great influence later on. They were the origin of the concept of logical grammar (or logical syntax). A grammatical syntax takes into account only the basic syntactic categories and the rules for creating derived categories. But this type of grammar only considers sentences that have a correct grammatical structure, such as "Peter is a prime number". In contrast, a logical syntax goes beyond grammatical syntax, as it establishes the admissible categorial combinations by including semantic compatibility rules. This system avoids erroneous and metaphysical statements and allows scientific knowledge to be expressed in a meaningful language that has a connection or correspondence with reality. In [Carnap, 1993], this issue of meaningful and non-significant language is described.

In "Meaning and Necessity", Carnap makes the observation that Frege's concept of "meaning" should be recursive, that we would need "sense of meaning", etc., i.e., an infinite hierarchy of semantic denotations.


Meinong

Alexius Meinong's object theory is based on the correspondence or identification between objects and thoughts. It is a very simple and straightforward theory:
Wittgenstein

Like Frege, the first Wittgenstein (the one of the Tractatus) distinguished between Sinn (sense) and Bedeutung (reference): The second Wittgenstein (that of Philosophical Investigations):
Strawson

Peter Strawson, in his essay "On Referring" [1950] criticizes Russell's theory of descriptions, the theory proposed 45 years earlier and which up to that time was considered a paradigm of analytic philosophy. Strawson advocated a method called "connective analysis": our concepts form a network in which concepts are nodes. An analysis of a concept involves analyzing the nearest concepts in the network. The goal of the analysis is to clearly identify the connections between the most general concepts of everyday language in order to carry out a descriptive metaphysics.


Putnam

For the philosopher Hilary Putnam meanings are not subjective, they are not in the head. To prove it, he proposes the mental experiment of "the twin Earth":
There is another planet Earth (T2) that is exactly like ours (T1). In T2 the liquid of rivers, lakes and seas is apparently identical to water, but that its chemical composition is not H2O but XYZ. A ship arrives at T2 from T1. Its crew members see the liquid and call it "water", because they observe that it is the same as the water they know in T1. Therefore, the term "water" has the same meaning for them on the two planets. When it was subsequently discovered that the composition of the "water" of T2 is different from that of T11, then the meaning would change: TT2 would be passed to mean the liquid whose component is XYZ.
Putnam's conclusion is that the reference of the term "water" is not a function of the speaker's psychological content. Meanings are not subjective and subjective meaning does not determine reference.


Donnellan

Philosopher Keith Donnellan has contributed to the philosophy of language, especially on the topic of the analysis of proper names and definite descriptions. The essay "Reference and Definite Descriptions" [1966] is a critique of Russell and Strawson's theory of definite descriptions. It states that it is necessary to differentiate between the referential use and the attributive use of definite descriptions, which are two uses or ways of referring to an object:
Kripke

Saul Kripke's [1995] book "Naming and Necessity", published in 1980, is considered one of the most important philosophical works of the 20th century. In it he critically examines traditional philosophical problems, and approaches in a new way the meaning-reference issue (as opposed to the prevailing ideas of Frege and Russell), especially the issue of proper names in the philosophy of language. Kripke's theories are more philosophical than linguistic, more oriented to metaphysical theses and less to the explanation of linguistic phenomena. Although his philosophical theses are based on the linguistic.
Dummet

Michael Dummet claims that Frege has been misunderstood on the subject of proper names. That Frege admitted that a proper name can have several different senses associated with it by different speakers. And that Frege used definite descriptions as examples of possible senses associated with a proper name.

For Dummet, "sense" is a component of meaning, precisely the one that makes it possible to "grasp" the reference. That is to say, meaning is the factor that makes it possible to find the reference, to understand the words and sentences and to discover whether they are true or false. Something that has meaning is something that makes us think of the reference, even if it does not exist. If sense is the ability to grasp the reference, then the sense of a proper name is the ability to find its reference, without any description of the reference.

According to Dummet, Frege fails in trying to explain the notion of sense because circularity occurs: sense is what makes us understand the expressions of language; but we can only know what the sense of an expression is if we already know the language. If Frege's thesis that the sense of a proper name is the sense of a description associated with it is accepted, two things remain to be explained: 1) the sense of a description; 2) the meaning of "sense".


Meaning and Denotation in MENTAL

In MENTAL we are dealing with an ideal language, not a natural one. Nevertheless, it provides a point of view that clarifies the concepts of meaning and denotation.

In the meaning-denotation issue of descriptive expressions we find ourselves, once again, with the internal-external or generic-specific or universal-particular or deep-surface duality, aspects that in MENTAL are united and harmonized from the perspective of the archetypes of consciousness. The problem of the conceptualization of meaning (or sense) and denotation (or reference), as well as the relationship between the two, is clarified and simplified notably: meaning and denotation are two united and complementary aspects of every expression. Expressions connect on the one hand with the deep (the meaning), and on the other they connect with the superficial (the denotation or reference). This conception coincides with that of Frege, who stated that linguistic signs connect meaning and reference.
Characteristics
Properties

In the subject of meaning (or sense) and denotation (or reference), immediate substitution, potential substitution (representation), and equivalence play essential roles. The following properties are satisfied:
Examples
  1. ((a = c) (b = c)) // a and b have the same reference: c

  2. 2+3 and 3+2 have the same reference: 5

  3. a+b and b+a have the same reference (since the sum is commutative), the two expressions are equivalent

  4. ( a★3 ) and aaa have the same reference: aaa, since the first expression represents the second one

  5. (a a a a) and aaa have the same reference: aaa, since the second expression is a shortened form of the first one

  6. ( 1…4 ) and 1234 have the same reference and different meaning (the first expression is a representation of the second one)

  7. In (x =: (a b c)), the expression x represents and has reference to (a b c).

  8. The expressions ( 1…4 ), 1234 and (1 2 3 4) have different meanings and the same reference: 1234.

  9. The expressions (a b c)/(b=12) and (a 12 c) have the same reference, which is the last expression

  10. If we have the expression ⟨( f(x y) = (x+y x*y) )⟩, then f(r1 r2) has the same reference as f(r2 r1), whichever r1 or r2, since the sum and product of real numbers are commutative.

Russell's theory of descriptions

Russell's theory of descriptions is a restrictive theory:

Addenda

The descriptions defined in Principia Mathematica

Definite descriptions are described in a more technical way in Russell and Whitehead's Principia Mathematica. They used the notation ιxFx (the object x described by Fx), "ι" being the Greek letter "iota". According to its authors, this expression is not a formula, but a term.


The problem of the existential predicate in Russell

On something that does not exist one cannot assign a predicate because it leads to contradictions. For example, if we say that "The current king of France does not exist" −in traditional notation NoExists(F), being F "The current king of France"), and in MENTAL F/(Exists')F has the property of "non-existence".

But for an object to have properties it is necessary that it exists (what does not exist cannot have properties) . If an object exists, it has properties, and if it has properties it exists. If F has the property of non-existence, then this means that it exists. Therefore, F exists and does not exist at the same time. Contradiction.

To solve this problem, there are two solutions:
  1. An object can have properties without existing. To have properties it is enough to "be". Being is a deeper ontological level than existing, which is more superficial. F has properties because it "is". Therefore, F does not exist and is, which is not a contradiction. This is the solution given by Russell in "The Principles of Mathematics" (1903).

  2. Every definite description exists. Therefore, F exists and, therefore, properties can be assigned to it, the contradiction disappearing. This is the solution offered by Russell in his 1905 article (On Denoting)

Bibliography