MENTAL
 Main Menu
 Applications
 Philosophy
 MENTAL as Truth


MENTAL as Truth
 MENTAL AS TRUTH

"Truth is indefinable" (Gottlob Frege).

"Truth is the all" (Hegel)

"Truth can be recognized by its beauty and simplicity" (Richard Feynman).

"Truth is not found in the heights, but in the depths of things" (Paul Twitchell).



What is Truth?

Truth has been one of the fundamental subjects of reflection throughout history, mainly by theologians, philosophers, psychologists, linguists, logicians and mathematicians. It is a theme associated with the search for the essence and foundation of everything. As a concept, truth is presented as something diffuse, elusive, inapprehensible. That is why it has various definitions and interpretations, which are not necessarily mutually exclusive. But an integrative or unifying approach as knowledge, as value, as theory, as practice, as communication and as utility has not yet been achieved.

On the subject of truth, different questions arise, among them the following:
The Conceptions of Truth

Truth is conceived in many different ways, among them the following:
Truth as correspondence

According to the correspondence theory, a proposition is true if and only if it corresponds to a fact in the real world. Truth is a correspondence between what is said and what is. It is the most widespread and accepted interpretation of truth. It is present in pre-Socratic philosophy and is explicit in Plato: "True is the speech that says things as they are, false is the speech that says them as they are not". Here Plato implicitly affirms that truth is a relation between language (or thought), and that language is broader (has more possibilities) than reality.

Aristotle, in his Metaphysics, states, "To deny what is or to affirm what is not, is false, whereas to affirm what is and to deny what is not, is true." Here the Stagirite extends Plato's assertion by positing four alternatives, instead of the Platonic two:

Truth valuePlatoAristotle extension.
TrueAffirming what isDenying what is not
FalseTo affirm what is notTo deny what is

Russell, at the time he defended the theory of logical atomism, held that truth is a correspondence between a proposition and a fact (or state of affairs): a true proposition and the fact to which it refers share the same structure.

The first Wittgenstein (the one of the Tractatus), with his figurative theory of meaning, establishes that there is a correspondence between language and reality, like that between a painting and reality. For the second Wittgenstein (that of Philosophical Investigations), the meaning of a linguistic expression is its use, so that the meaning of truth varies according to circumstances or cultural context.

For Davidson, facts, in themselves, are true sentences. And facts are not referenced by propositions.

Austin held that there need not be a structural or formal parallel between a true proposition and the state of affairs that makes it true. It is only necessary that the semantics of the language in which the proposition is expressed correlate the proposition with the state of affairs.

The correspondence theory has been the object of criticism, among them: 1) It does not clarify in what that relation or correspondence consists between what is said and what is; 2) It is a superficial theory that only tries to link or connect the mental world (thought, language) and the physical world.


The deflationary theory of truth

The deflationary theory of truth asserts that saying a statement is true is equivalent to asserting the statement itself. For example, "'Snow is white' is true" is equivalent to "Snow is white." The predicate "is true" assigned to a sentence does not add new knowledge, it is redundant, insubstantial. The predicate "truth" does not express a property. The belief that truth is a property is an illusion caused by the fact that we have the predicate "is true" in natural language.

This theory is called "deflationist" because the concept of truth loses its value. The deflationist theory is advocated by Frege, Wittgenstein, Ramsey, Rorty, Harwich, Quine, and Strawson.
Truth in Logic and Mathematics

Truth in Logic

Traditional logic is based on the assignment to every proposition of a truth value: T (true) or F (false).

Classical logic has been restricted by two laws concerning T and F:
  1. The law of the excluded third party. Every proposition is T or F. There is no other intermediate value.

  2. The law of no−contradiction. No proposition can be both T and F.
This duality of logical values has been generalized. The most complete generalization is the one that admits infinitely many intermediate values between 0 (representing F) and 1 (representing T).

We must distinguish between propositions and sentences (or statements): A proposition need not be known or manifested in any given language to be true.

There are sentences that are disputed as to whether they have truth value. For example, "The present king of France is bald" is false for Russell, and neither true nor false for Strawson (so it would not be a proposition).

Expressions about the future (such as "It will rain tomorrow") are disputed as to whether they have truth value or whether it is unknown.
Truth in mathematics

In mathematics, truth is associated with proof. A statement is true if it is deducible from a set of axioms and the rules of derivation (or inference) of a consistent formal axiomatic system. A system is consistent if one cannot deduce one thing and the opposite. In mathematical expressions, "validity" is what counts, not "truth".

For Hilbert, the prime mover of the formal axiomatic method, truth and demonstrability are the same thing. According to this author, the formal axiomatic method is the "philosopher's stone" of mathematics, the source of all mathematical truths. But Gödel proved, with his incompleteness theorem, that in formal axiomatic systems there are indemonstrable truths.

Mathematics transcends the physical world. This became clear with the appearance of alternative geometries to Euclidean geometry in the 19th century, by modifying the axiom of parallels (the famous fifth postulate), as consistent as Euclidean geometry. Euclidean geometry was supposed to be the only "true" −evident, according to Kant−, since it expressed the reality of the physical world. But infinite possible alternative geometries can be constructed that are perfectly consistent. No geometry is truer than any other, nor can the truth of any of them be affirmed. At the mathematical level they are all valid. The discovery of non-Euclidean geometries opened the field of geometry to new horizons of freedom and creativity. And with them, imaginary mathematics and mathematical relativism were born, as geometric relativism spread to other branches of mathematics: This philosophy corresponds to that of an open mathematics, dependent only on the axioms to be established.

Model theory goes beyond specific formal axiomatic systems. A model is an interpretation of a formal axiomatic system among the various possible interpretations. In model theory, the notion of truth is relative to the structure of the formal axiomatic system. A proposition is true if its structure satisfies that system at the structural level, independently of its interpretations.

This view generalizes to all formal definitions to arrive at an "imaginary mathematics". Imaginary numbers, dual numbers, surreal numbers, and hypernumbers fall into this category.

These discoveries highlighted that mathematics transcended physical reality. The physical universe is only a particular case of the mathematical universe. Mathematics is open, infinite and belongs to a realm superior to the physical, an abstract realm that is the foundation of the mental world.
Formal Theories of Truth

Tarski's semantic theory of truth

Tarski's theory of truth is the most widely accepted and well-known formal theory of truth, although it is not without its critics. It is considered the successor theory of correspondentism. He disclosed it in his essay "The Semantic Conception of Truth and the Foundations of Semantics" (1930) and "The Concept of Truth in Formalized Languages" (1935).

His theory is based on the central idea that in order to define truth it is necessary to distinguish between object language and metalanguage (a language that speaks of the object language), or else a single language that distinguishes between linguistic and metalinguistic aspects. The metalanguage must contain sufficient expressive means to be able to refer to the object language, i.e. it must be at least as rich as the object language. And both languages must be formalized. Tarski proved that the concept of truth is indefinable in a formalized language: "A language strong enough to express arithmetic and in which classical logic is valid is inconsistent, because in such a language the liar can be formalized" ('this sentence is false')". It is a theorem that he included in his 1935 paper. Tarski was the first to show clearly that there could never be a formal definition of the predicate "truth" in a language, because its definition leads to contradictions.

Tarski's theory is a semantic theory of truth. It relates the syntactic level (purely formal) and the epistemological level (of interpretation). And it is a correspondent theory between language and reality, which follows Aristotle's criterion.

Criticism:
Kripke: truth as a "fixed point"

Tarski's hierarchical approach was the dominant answer to the problem of semantic paradoxes. But in 1975, Kripke in his famous and influential paper "Outline of a Theory of Truth" [1975] proposed a semantic theory of truth that represented an advance over Tarsky's theory.

For Kripke, the construction of the hierarchical truth predicates of Tarsky's theory is a particular case of a more general approach: the "fixed point approach". The main points of this theory are: Kripke thus showed that a language can consistently contain its own truth predicate, which Tarski considered impossible, since truth belongs to the metalanguage. Kripke's method allows the definition of the predicate "truth" within the language itself, but at the cost of extending the logic to three truth values, where the laws of the excluded third and of non-contradiction are not fulfilled.


Davidson's theory of meaning

Davidson attempted to apply Tarski's definition of truth to natural languages to create a theory of meaning:
The search for truth in Descartes

Descartes developed the hypothesis of the evil god (or genius) in his work "Metaphysical Meditations" in which he culminates his system of the search for truth through methodical doubt: Descartes' aim was to investigate the possibility of finding something that is absolutely indubitable, not subject to possible deception or impossible to be deceived.


MENTAL as Truth

MENTAL provides a general framework of truth:
Truth is the essence of all that exists

What is truth? Truth is the absolute, the permanent, the permanent, the stable, the necessary, that which cannot be questioned, that which is always present in all things and cannot be avoided, the essence of everything. The essence of reality is abstraction in its highest expression, the deepest, that which is common to everything, the simplest: the philosophical categories, the primal archetypes, the universal semantic primitives. The true nature of a model of reality encoded with MENTAL is precisely its code, which conceptually connects the internal and the external.

At the deep level the truth is contacted. At this level the concepts of truth, maximum abstraction, maximum simplicity, maximum freedom, maximum consciousness, maximum power and maximum creativity are integrated.

MENTAL is the solid and unquestionable truth sought by Descartes, for it is the foundation of possible worlds. Every possible world is governed by the primitives of MENTAL.



Addenda

The cube, symbol of truth

The cube is the symbol of truth, stability, wisdom, perfection and totality. It shows all its faces equal, without hiding anything. It is also the symbol of the multiple and harmonious union of opposites. Truth is eternal and not subject to change. The unfolded (open) cube forms a cross, the symbol of the universal, eternal and prototypical man, the human connection with the universal truth.


Bibliography