MENTAL
 Main Menu
 Problematic
 Limitations of Logic


02. Limitations of Logic
 LIMITATIONS
OF LOGIC

"We are less certain than ever about the ultimate foundations of logic and mathematics" (Hermann Weil),

"Logic has no existence independent of mathematics" (Tobias Dantzig).

"Logic fills the world; the limits of the world are also its limits" (Wittgenstein).



The Logics

Mathematical Logic

Historically, mathematics and logic have been distinct disciplines. But modernly logic has become more mathematical and mathematics more logical. Today it is impossible to draw a dividing line between the two.

Mathematics formalized logic to create so-called "mathematical logic". Its main proponents were Boole, Peano, Frege and Russell:
The new logics.

Until practically the end of the 19th century there was only one logic, the classical Aristotelian logic. This logic was considered to be the only one that could exist, so this subject was considered complete and closed. Nowadays there is a profusion of different logics (besides the classical one): modal, fuzzy, linear, intuitionistic, paraconsistent, paracomplete, equational, etc. . These logics have been created so that they could be applied to specific domains (computer science, artificial intelligence, cognition, etc.), since classical logic is not sufficiently generic and flexible.

Faced with this situation of confusion, it becomes necessary to go towards the foundation of logic, in the abstract, to search for its essence and to see if all these logics can be derived from a fundamental logic, which we can call "generic", "abstract" or "universal".

For this, what is needed is not a symbolic formalization, but a philosophical logic, a logic based on primitive concepts. Formalism must be discarded, because it is a mere game of manipulation of symbols, by means of certain rules, a blind mechanism, without semantics.

Characteristics of this universal logic must be: The development of non-classical logics began on May 18, 1910, when the logician and philosopher Nikolai Vasiliev published the article "On Partial Judgments, Triangle of Opposition, Law of the Excluding Room", in which he expounded the principles of an "imaginary logic", inspired by Lobatchevsky's non-Euclidean geometry (also initially qualified by its author as "imaginary"). In the same way that this geometry relaxes Euclid's V postulate (the postulate of parallels), in imaginary logic the principle of contradiction and the law of the exclusive third are relaxed to admit three kinds of judgments: affirmative, negative and indifferent. This new logic, like imaginary geometry, was also consistent (or paraconsistent, i.e., with a certain tolerance of contradiction).

This new logic was justified for several reasons: Vasiliev did not make a formal development of his ideas. A.I. Arruda [1977] formalized some of Vasiliev's ideas.

There is a great variety of specialized logics, without a common root, i.e. without a basic or fundamental logic from which to derive all other logics (see Addendum).


Limitations of formal logic.

The limitations of formal logic (or mathematical logic) are the following:
The concept of "truth"

The concept of "truth" is linked to logic and should be something essentially "logical". However, it is a controversial and ambiguous concept. It is better to replace the concept "truth" by that of "existence", which is much more general and more concrete, less fuzzy and more manageable:
Logical paradoxes.

Logical paradoxes have traditionally been considered a source of problems for mathematics, to the point that they have affected its very foundation.

The most famous paradox is what we call today "Russell's paradox": "Does the set of sets that do not belong to themselves belong to themselves?". Put another way: "The set whose elements are all the sets that are not elements of themselves, is it or is it not an element of itself?". The answer to this question is both true and false. This paradox arose out of Frege's attempts to formalize Cantor's set theory, and which Russell communicated to Frege in 1902. In general, Russell's paradox states that it is not possible to assume that every property determines a set of entities having that property, since some properties lead to contradiction.

Paradoxes arise from the confluence of two circumstances: self-references and true-false dualism. But paradoxes disappear when truth or falsity is considered as a mere attribute of a mathematical entity, and self-references become, as we shall see, fractal expressions (expressions in which the same pattern is repeated indefinitely). The concept of fractal is of great importance, since it is linked to the structure of the mind, consciousness and reality itself.

Paradoxes are in fact expressions of consciousness, since two opposite concepts meet or converge. And not only should we not reject them, but we should accept them because they are precisely the expressions that have the greatest power. Paradoxes do not take us away from the truth and the fundamentals, but quite the contrary.


Formal axiomatic systems.

Mathematics, since Euclid, uses the axiomatic method. A formal axiomatic system is composed of: A formal axiomatic system must fulfill three properties:
  1. Consistency. It must not be possible to prove a formula and its negation.

  2. Completeness. All valid formulas (true under any interpretation) must be provable.

  3. Decidability. There must be an effective method for deciding whether a formula is true or false.
But the axiomatic method presents problems: In the latter aspect, 3 rules are usually used:
  1. Union rule:
    If A and B are theorems, then AB (logical conjunction) is also.

  2. Rule of separation (modus ponens):
    If A and AB (logical implication) are theorems, then B is a theorem.

  3. Substitution rule:
    If A is a theorem in which p1, ... , pn and B1, ... , Bn appear. ,Bn are sentences, then substituting in A p1=B1, ... , pn=Bn, is a theorem.
In Principia Mathematica these three rules were used.

In propositional logic, the rules of separation and substitution are used. The rule of union is not a rule of inference but a constructive rule.

Robinson's resolution principle uses only one rule: From AB and A∨¬B follows A.

But the only "natural" rule to apply is the rule of separation, as already intuited by Peano and also defended by Russell in "The Principles of Mathematics": "When our minds are fixed on inference, it seems natural to take 'implication' as the fundamental primitive relation."



Addendum

The different logics.

The following list of logics is not necessarily exhaustive:

Absolute, abstract, adaptive, affine, algebraic, defeasible (defeasible), Aristotelian, binary, categorical, class, combinatorial, compact, computational, quantum, quantificational, Horn clause, belief, decision, demonstration, intention, obligation logics, knowledge, deontic, deontic, descriptions, transitions, deviant, dialectic, dynamic, fuzzy, divergent, doxistic (of beliefs), equational, epistemic, epistemic, spatial, structural, erethic (of the art of asking questions), extensional, fractal, general, Hoare's, identity, IF, inexact, infinitary, intensional, intuitionistic, lambda, free, linear, matrix, mereological (that of the whole and the parts), modal (of necessity and possibility), multidimensional, multivariate (many-sorted logic), non-monotonic, ordinal, paraclassical, paracomplete, paraconsistent, plural, polyvalent (or plurivalent or multivalued), default, Port-Royal, first-order predicate, higher-order, preference, product (or tetravalent), propositional (or zero-order), fixed-point, relational, relevance, substructural, temporal, term, trivalent, topological, transconsistent, validation.


Bibliography