MENTAL
 Main Menu
 Problematic
 Limitations of Mathematics


Limitations of Mathematics
 LIMITATIONS OF
MATHEMATICS

"It is common to speak of 'the language of mathematics.' But is mathematics truly a language?" (F. David Peat)

"In order to interpret mathematical notation it is you need to know what kind of grammar it uses" (Stephen Wolfram)

"The essence of mathematics lies in its complete freedom" (Cantor)



The Nature of Mathematics

Historically, there has been a long controversy over the question of the nature of mathematics. Surprisingly, today we still do not know exactly what it is. It is often claimed that it is better not to define mathematics because, if this were done, it would mean limiting it, circumscribing its domain.

The question "What is mathematics?" has had different answers throughout history, among them the following: Among all these answers, the first answer is the highest of all: mathematics as the science of consciousness. From it, all other conceptions must be consequences.


Weak foundation

Without a knowledge of the true nature or essence of mathematics we can hardly ground it. The foundations of mathematics (known in abbreviated form as FOM, "Foundations of Mathematics") is the study of its most basic or fundamental concepts and the relationships (structural and functional) between them. It may seem surprising, but mathematics, a key science that underpins our society, lacks solid foundations or it is not known what exactly its foundations consist of.

FOM is a subject of enormous importance from a theoretical and practical as well as a philosophical and psychological point of view. Today there is a renewed interest in this subject because it is recognized that a true structure of mathematics as a system and as a language is lacking.

One often speaks of the philosophy of mathematics, of the philosophy derived from mathematics. But the point of view must be the opposite: mathematics must be grounded in philosophy. Mathematics cannot ground itself. Its foundations have to be deeper: they have to be philosophical.


Fragmentation

Mathematics has become a tower of Babel, as it has become progressively fragmented into more or less scattered branches or domains: The fragmentation of mathematics began in the early 18th century and acquired a pathological character in the 20th century, with a division into increasingly specialized domains. Many of these domains disappeared, others flourished. The result has been the extinction of the species of generalist or universalist mathematicians, whose last exponents were Henri Poincaré and John Von Neumann.

The AMS (American Mathematical Society) lists 50 major mathematical specialties, ranging from algebraic topology to Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory. These specialties are further divided into more than 300 subspecialties.

It is perhaps because of so much fragmentation that they are called "mathematics," plural, for there are many and diverse. Mathematics urgently needs a unified language, with a common conceptual basis, connecting the different domains.


Paradigms

A paradigm is "a view of the world", a form of abstraction of reality. Throughout history there have been different mathematical paradigms, which have been based on only one concept (or conceptual paradigm). The concepts that have been used have been number, set, structure, function and category.

But what we need is a change of paradigm, but not just another one, but a new paradigm of a global and unifying type. A paradigm that must be based on a few primitive concepts and that will allow the rest of the paradigms to be founded and expressed. These primitive concepts should be understood in as simple terms as possible. From these primitive concepts it should be possible to define new (derived) concepts in an environment that facilitates expressiveness and creativity. This unifying approach is precisely the one being followed by physics, which seeks a "theory of everything," although in this case "everything" refers only to the physical world.


Restricted concepts

Mathematical concepts, in general, are usually restricted. But fundamental mathematical concepts should be universal or have the maximum possible generality, depth and abstraction. But they should fulfill three conditions, which are related to each other:

✲ Genericity.
Any fundamental or primary mathematical concept must be generic. Secondary concepts must be derivable from primary concepts. For example:
  • The concept of imaginary number. If imaginary numbers exist, genericity demands that all kinds of imaginary expressions must exist: imaginary sets, imaginary functions, imaginary categories, etc.

  • At the level of the mathematical domain, if there is imaginary arithmetic, there must also be imaginary algebra, imaginary logic, imaginary geometry, and so on. And if there exists a fuzzy (or fuzzy) logic, there must also exist a fuzzy arithmetic, a fuzzy algebra, etc.

  • The concept of vector, defined as an oriented line segment. Its generalization is the multivector: oriented segments of two or more dimensions. This concept, in this case, does exist and was conceived by Grassmann.

  • Parameterization. The only mathematical object that can be parameterized is a function. But this concept should be applicable to any mathematical object: a set, a sequence, a number, and so on.

  • If there are classes or categories of sets or functions, there should also be classes or categories for all kinds of mathematical objects, without exception. For example, categories of functions of functions, categories of logical expressions, categories of numbers, etc.
✲ Orthogonality.
Orthogonality refers to the free combinatorics of concepts, entities, objects or mathematical expressions, without restrictions of any kind. For example:
  • A function should be able to return as a result any mathematical object: a function, a higher-order function, a numerical range, a set, a sequence of sets, etc.

  • Concepts such as matrices and vectors are composed of "numbers". This is restrictive. They should be able to be composed of any kind of expressions and not just numbers. For example, matrices of vectors, vectors of matrices, vectors of functions, etc.

  • Logical operations are not generic as they apply only on logical expressions, i.e., those that evaluate to V (true) or F (false).

  • Arithmetic operations are not generic either since they apply only on numbers or on variables. They cannot be applied over functions, sets, logical values, etc.

  • Predicates (or attributes) should be able to be applied to any mathematical object (a function, a set, etc.).

  • The condition is applied to specify elements of a set that have a certain property. There is no standard notation. It is usually represented as "|" (vertical bar) or ";" (semicolon). Neither of these symbols corresponds to an operator with defined semantics. For example, {n | nNn>5} (specifies the set of natural numbers greater than 5). But the condition must be applicable to any type of mathematical object (if the condition is met, that object is selected).
✲ Reflexivity.
When a concept is used, there must always be higher-order concepts, i.e., there must be reflection or conceptual recursion: every concept must also be applicable to itself. Thus arise concepts of concepts (concepts of order 2), concepts of concepts of concepts (concepts of order 3), and so on. In reality it is an auto-orthogonality, that is, a conceptual combinatoriality with the concept itself. And this mechanism should also be reflected in the different mathematical domains, there should be a higher order arithmetic, a higher order logic, a higher order geometry, etc. For example:
  • Higher-order imaginary expressions: numbers of numbers, imaginary numbers of imaginary numbers, imaginary functions of imaginary functions, functions of functions, vectors of vectors, matrices of matrices, multivectors of multivectors, predicates of predicates, etc.

  • There are the arithmetic operators addition, product (sum of sums) and exponentiation (product of products), but there is no standard notation for higher-order operations (exponentiation of exponentiations, etc.).

  • If the concept of infinitesimal exists, there must exist infinitesimals of higher order. And the same with infinite numbers, although this aspect Cantor tried to cover with his transfinite numbers.

  • Every parameterized expression must be able to be, in turn, parameterized (parameterized expressions of higher order).

The mathematical language

It is common to speak of "mathematical language", but mathematics lacks a formal language. For it to have one, it would need: Traditional languages are defined by a formal (or syntactic) grammar. But mathematics is not a language anymore, it is not a concrete language, it is a universal language, and it cannot be limited by a formal grammar. Therefore:
Lack of humanism

Mathematics has become a complex discipline, difficult to understand, with concepts that are generally not very intuitive and with a somewhat esoteric notation. In short, a not very humanistic discipline, out of the common culture, only for "initiates".

The essayist and poet Hans Magnus Enzensberger [2001] asks: "How is it possible that mathematics has remained a kind of blind spot in our culture, as if it were a foreign territory?".

This situation is paradoxical, because mathematics, if it is the foundation of the formal sciences, should have very simple foundations and be integrated into human culture.

Historically, mathematics has been considered an absolute, perfect, precise, objective and universal discipline, independent of cultural or epistemological context. However, all these characteristics have been declining, especially with the emergence of the humanistic mathematics movement. Humanistic mathematics is a philosophy that attempts to seek the human side of mathematical thinking in two main aspects: 1) Mathematics grounded in humanism; 2) Humanistic teaching/learning of mathematics.

The characteristics of humanistic mathematics are:

Addendum

Some proposals on the "new mathematics"
History of humanistic mathematics

Humanism dates back to the ancient Greeks, Chinese Confucianism and the Renaissance. It is a philosophy that places man, with his possibilities and his limitations, as the foundation and center of all things, so that: Humanistic mathematics is an idea that dates back to Plato and has been advocated by different mathematicians throughout history by highlighting the role of intuition, imagination and creativity in mathematical ideas.

Humanism as a formal school in philosophy of mathematics was created by Reuben Hersh in 1979 [Hersch, 1999].

The modern revitalization of this subject is mainly due to Alvin White [1993]. In 1986 he organized a conference, attended by mathematicians, philosophers, and educators, to discuss the relationship between mathematics and humanism and to try to discover what was wrong with mathematics education. The enthusiastic response led to the creation of the "Humanistic Mathematics Newsletter" in 1987. In 1992 it became the "Humanistic Mathematics Network Journal". It is currently published only on the Internet.


Bibliography